© SEATTLE JOURNAL FOR SOCIAL JUSTICE, VOLUME 11 • ISSUE 1 • 2012
I. INTRODUCTION
Many Americans were outraged when the Wall Street banks paid out an estimated $18.4 billion in executive and staff bonuses in 2009, even while the economy was being cratered by the financial meltdown and the Great Recession.2 It seemed very unfair to many Americans that the perpetrators were being rewarded while the victims were paying a terrible price. Indeed, the stock market meltdown and the loss of home values in the subprime mortgage fiasco reduced the total net worth of American families by $16.4 trillion (about 25 percent), while 8.8 million workers lost their jobs and $700 billion in taxpayer money was appropriated to rescue the banks.3 The widespread perception that the bankers had avoided the consequences of their actions (“moral hazard” is the textbook term for it) helped to fuel the Occupy Wall Street movement that erupted last year. This notorious episode demonstrates that fairness is not just a philosophical construct or a legal principle; it is a “gut issue” that pervades our social, economic, and political lives. We now know that a sense of fairness is a deeply rooted aspect of human psychology, and a battleground where many of our political battles are fought. In fact, fairness has emerged as a central issue in the 2012 election. For example, President Obama invoked variations on the term “fairness” no less than fourteen times in his important Osawatomie speech at the end of 2011.4
The underlying reason for the public distress about fairness, however, goes far beyond Wall Street bonuses. This infamous incident was only a symptom of much deeper problems with our capitalist economic system, including the extreme concentration of wealth among a small percentage of the population, the ever-widening gap between the super-rich and the rest of us, and the spreading sea of poverty (or near poverty) that now afflicts about one-third of our population.5 A growing number of Americans believe that our economy is fundamentally unfair.
In my 2011 book, The Fair Society, 6 I argue that the implicit “social contract” that binds together any reasonably stable and harmonious society is breaking down in this country, with ominous potential consequences, and that it is time to redefine fairness and rewrite the social contract in a way that puts fairness first. In this article, I provide a synopsis of this argument and outline some of the public policy implications.
II. THE SCIENCE OF HUMAN NATURE
Some cynics view fairness as nothing more than a mask for self-interest. As the playwright George Bernard Shaw put it, “The golden rule is that there is no golden rule.”7 But the cynics are wrong. An important finding of the emerging, multi-disciplinary science of human nature is that humans do, indeed, have an innate sense of fairness. We regularly display a concern for others’ interests as well as our own, and we even show a willingness to punish perceived acts of unfairness. The accumulating evidence for this distinctive human trait, which spans a dozen different scientific disciplines, suggests that our sense of fairness has played an important role in our evolution as a species. Most likely, it served to facilitate and lubricate the close-knit social organization that has been a key to our success as a species. While this evidence is reviewed in some detail in my book, the following is a brief summary.
In the field of behavior genetics, many studies have documented that there is a genetic basis for traits that are strongly associated with fairness, including altruism, empathy, and nurturance. In the brain sciences, the experiments of Joshua Greene and his colleagues identified specific brain areas associated with making moral choices.8 Another team, headed by Alan Sanfey, pinpointed an area of the brain specifically associated with feelings of fairness and unfairness when subjects participated in the so-called “ultimatum game” in his laboratory.9 Yet another source of evidence involves the biochemistry of the brain. In a series of laboratory experiments, neuro-economist Paul Zak and his colleagues have demonstrated that a uniquely mammalian brain chemical, oxytocin, is strongly associated with acts of giving and reciprocating.10 These experiments have also shown that artificial enhancement of oxytocin levels in the brain can augment the behavioral effects.11
Especially compelling is the evidence, reported by anthropologist Donald Brown in his landmark study, Human Universals, that altruism, reciprocity, and a concern for fairness are cultural universals.12 There is also the extensive research by evolutionary psychologists Leda Cosmedes and John Tooby, as well as a number of their colleagues, on what they term “social exchange” (i.e., reciprocity)—which they point out also exists in every culture.13 Cosmedes and Tooby have concluded that humans possess a discreet “mental module”—a dedicated neurocognitive system—for reciprocity behaviors. In a similar vein, the work on “strong reciprocity theory” in experimental and behavioral economics has repeatedly shown that even altruistic behaviors can be elicited in cooperative situations if there is a combination of strict reciprocity and punishment for defectors.14 Finally, it has been shown that even some nonhuman primates display in a rudimentary form some of the traits associated with fairness behaviors in humans.15 For instance, primatologist Frans de Waal, in a classic laboratory experiment, clearly demonstrated the existence of reciprocity behaviors in capuchin monkeys.16
It seems evident that a sense of fairness is an inborn human trait. This means, quite simply, that we are inclined to take into account and accommodate the needs and interests of others. However, it is equally clear that our sense of fairness is labile. It can be subverted by various cultural, economic, and political influences, not to mention the lure of our selfinterests. And, of course, there are always the “outliers” like the Bernie Madoffs.
In fact, our predisposition toward fairness, like every other biological trait, is subject to significant individual variation. Numerous studies have indicated that approximately 20–30 percent of us are more or less “fairness challenged.”17 Some of us are so self-absorbed and egocentric that we are completely insensitive and even hostile to the needs of others. Although Ebenezer Scrooge (in Charles Dickens’s A Christmas Carol), and the banker Henry F. Potter (in Frank Capra’s timeless Christmas movie, It’s a Wonderful Life) are caricatures, many of us have seen likenesses of these characters in real life.
III. THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
Our variability as a species means that fairness is not a given. It is an end that can only be approximated with consistent effort, often in the face of strong opposition. And in many cases where there are conflicting fairness claims, compromise is the indispensable solvent for achieving a voluntary, consensual outcome. At the individual level, fairness is an issue in all of our personal relationships—with our families, with our loved ones, with our friends, and with our coworkers. We are confronted almost every day with concerns about providing or doing our fair share, reciprocating for some kindness, recognizing the rights of other persons, or being fairly acknowledged and rewarded for our efforts.
Fairness is also an important, macro-level political issue in any society and the debate about social justice can be traced back at least to Plato’s great dialogue, The Republic. 18 For Plato, social justice consists of “giving every man his due” (and every woman, of course). His great student, Aristotle, characterized it as “proportionate equality.”19 Plato also advanced the idea that every society entails a social “compact”—a tacit understanding about the rights and duties, and benefits and costs, of citizenship—and he viewed social justice as the key to achieving a stable and harmonious society.
The idea that there is a more or less well-defined “social contract” in every society is commonly associated with the so-called social contract theorists of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, such as Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, and, more recently, John Rawls. Rousseau fantasized about free individuals voluntarily forming communities in which everyone was equal and all were subject to the “general will” (what we would call the “will of the people”). Hobbes, in contrast, envisioned a natural state of anarchic violence, and proposed, for the sake of mutual self-preservation, that everyone should be subject to the absolute “sovereign” authority of the state.20 Locke, on the other hand, rejected Hobbes’s dark vision. He conjured instead a benign state of nature in which free individuals voluntarily formed a limited contract for their mutual advantage but retained various residual rights.21
The philosopher David Hume and many others since have made a hash of this line of reasoning. In his devastating critique, A Treatise of Human Nature, Hume rejected the claim that some deep property of the natural world (natural laws), or some aspect of our history, could be used to justify moral precepts.22 Among other things, Hume pointed out that even if the origins of human societies actually conformed to such hypothetical motivations and scenarios (which we now know they did not), we have no logical obligation to accept an outdated social contract that was entered into by some remote ancestor. With the demise of the natural law argument, social contract theory has generally fallen into disfavor among philosophers, with the important exception of John Rawls. In his 1971 book, A Theory of Justice, Rawls provoked a widespread reconsideration of what constitutes fairness and social justice and, equally important, what precepts would produce a just society.23 Rawls proposed two complementary principles: (1) equality in the enjoyment of freedom (a concept fraught with complications), and (2) affirmative action (in effect) for “the least advantaged” among us. Relying on these principles, a just society would be achieved by ensuring that the poor have equal opportunities and that they receive a relatively larger share of any new wealth whenever the economic pie grows larger. Although philosophers and many others have exhaustively debated Rawls’s work, over the years, it seems to have had no discernible effect outside of academia.
There is one other major exception to the general decline of social contract theory, however, that is perhaps more significant than Rawls’s work. Over the past two decades, a number of behavioral economists, game theorists, evolutionary psychologists, and others have breathed new life into this venerable idea with a combination of rigorous, mathematically based game theory models and empirical research. Especially important is the work of the mathematician-turned-economist Ken Binmore, who has sought to use game theory as a tool for resuscitating social contract theory on a new footing. In his 2005 book, Natural Justice, Binmore describes his approach as a “scientific theory of justice” based on an evolutionary/adaptive perspective, as well as the growing body of research in behavioral and experimental economics regarding our evolved sense of fairness, plus some insights from game theory.24
Briefly, Binmore very broadly defines a social contract as any stable “coordination” of social behavior, such as our conventions about which side of the road we should drive on or pedestrian traffic patterns on sidewalks. Any sustained social interaction in what Binmore refers to as “the game of life”—such as a marriage, a car pool, or a bowling league—represents a tacit social contract if it is (1) stable, (2) efficient, and (3) fair.
To achieve a stable social contract, Binmore argues, a social relationship should strive for an equilibrium condition, an approximation of a Nash equilibrium in game theory. That is, the rewards or “payoffs” for each of the players should be optimized so that no one can improve on his or her own situation without exacting a destabilizing cost from the other cooperators. Ideally, then, a social contract is self-enforcing. As Binmore explains, it needs no social glue to hold it together because everyone is a willing participant and nobody has a better alternative. It is like a masonry arch that requires no mortar (a simile first used by Hume).
The problem with this formulation, as Binmore recognizes, is that it omits the radioactive core of the problem: how do you define fairness in substantive terms? As Binmore concedes, game theory “has no substantive content. . . . It isn’t our business to say what people ought to like.”25 Binmore rejects the very notion that there can be any universals where fairness is concerned. “The idea of a need is particularly fuzzy,” he tells us.26 In other words, Binmore’s version of a social contract involves an idealization, much like Plato’s republic, or utopian free market capitalism, or Karl Marx’s utopian socialism. Fairness is whatever people say it is, as long as they agree.
IV. THE “BIOSOCIAL CONTRACT”
I have taken a different approach. What I call a “biosocial contract” is distinctive in that it is grounded in our growing understanding of human nature and the basic (biological) purpose of a human society. It is focused on the content of fairness, and it encompasses a set of specific normative precepts. In the game theory paradigm, the social contract is all about harmonizing our personal interactions. “Well and good,” as the old saying goes. But in a biosocial contract, the players include all of the stakeholders in the political community and substantive fairness is the focus.
A biosocial contract is about the rights and duties of all of the stakeholders in society, both among themselves and in relation to the state. It is about defining what constitutes a “fair society.” It is a normative theory, but it is built on an empirical foundation. I believe it is legitimate to employ a normative theory in this case because life itself has a built-in normative bias—a normative preference, so to speak. We share with all other living things the biological imperatives associated with survival and reproduction (our basic needs). After all, if we want to survive and reproduce, if this is our shared biological objective, then certain principles of social intercourse follow as essential means to this end. In other words, a biosocial contract represents a “prudential” political road map that ultimately depends upon mutual consent.
First and foremost, a biosocial contract requires a major shift in our social values. The deep purpose of a human society is not, after all, about achieving growth, wealth, material affluence, power, or social equality, nor even about the pursuit of happiness. An organized society is quintessentially a “collective survival enterprise.” Whatever may be our perceptions, aspirations, or illusions (or for that matter, whatever may be our station in life), the basic problem for any society is to provide for the survival and reproductive needs of its members. This entails a broad array of fourteen basic needs domains, which are discussed in some detail in my book.27
However, it is also important to recognize our differences in merit and to reward (or punish) them accordingly. It is clear that “just desserts” are also fundamental to our sense of fairness, as the Wall Street bonus outrage illustrated. Finally, there must also be reciprocity—an unequivocal commitment on the part of all of the participants to help support the collective survival enterprise—for no society can long exist on a diet of altruism. Altruism is a means to a larger end, not an end in itself. It is the emotional and normative basis of our safety net.
Accordingly, the biosocial contract paradigm that I have proposed in my book encompasses three distinct normative (and policy) precepts that must be bundled together and balanced in order to approximate the Platonic ideal of social justice. These precepts are as follows:
- Goods and services must be distributed to each according to his or her basic needs (in this, there must be equality);
- Surpluses beyond the provisioning of our basic needs must be distributed according to “merit” (there must also be equity); and,
- In return, each of us is obligated to contribute to the collective survival enterprise proportionately in accordance with our ability (there must be reciprocity).
The first of these precepts, equality, involves a collective obligation to provide for the common needs of all of our people. It is grounded in four empirical propositions: (1) our basic needs are increasingly well documented; (2) although our individual needs may vary somewhat, in general they are equally shared; (3) we are dependent upon many others, and our economy as a whole, for the satisfaction of these needs; and (4) more or less severe harm will result if any of these needs are not satisfied. All of this is discussed at length in The Fair Society.28
Although this precept may sound socialistic, an echo of Karl Marx’s famous dictum, it is at once far more specific and more limited. It is not about an equal share of wealth, but refers specifically to the fourteen basic biological needs domains that are detailed in my book. Our basic needs are neither a vague, open-ended abstraction nor a matter of personal preference. They constitute a concrete but ultimately limited agenda, with measurable indicators for assessing outcomes.
These fourteen basic needs domains include a number of obvious items, like adequate nutrition, fresh water, physical safety, physical and mental health, and waste elimination, as well as some items that we may take for granted like thermoregulation (which can entail many different technologies, from clothing to heating oil and air conditioning), along with adequate sleep (about one-third of our lives), mobility, and even healthy respiration, which cannot always be assured. Perhaps least obvious, but most important, are the requisites for the reproduction and nurturance of the next generation. In other words, our basic needs cut a very broad swath through our economy and our society.
The idea that there is a “social right” to the necessities of life is not new. It is implicit in the Golden Rule, the great moral precept that is recognized by every major religion and culture.29 There is also a substantial scholarly literature on the need to establish constitutional and legal protections for social/economic rights that are comparable to political rights.30 Indeed, three important formal covenants have endorsed social rights, including the United Nations’ 1948 Universal Declaration of Human Rights,31 the Council of Europe’s 1961 European Social Charter,32 and the United Nations’ 1966 International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights,33 although these documents have been widely treated as aspirational rather than as legally enforceable.34
Perhaps more significant is the evidence of broad public support for the underlying principle of social rights. Over the years, numerous public opinion surveys have consistently shown that people are far more willing to provide aid for the genuinely needy than neo-classical (rational choice) economic theory would lead one to believe. (Some of these surveys are cited in my book.35) More compelling evidence of public support for social rights, I believe, can be found in the results of an extensive series of social experiments regarding distributive justice by political scientists Norman Frohlich and Joe Oppenheimer, and their colleagues, as detailed in their 1992 book Choosing Justice. 36 What Frohlich and Oppenheimer set out to test was whether ad hoc groups of “impartial” decision-makers, behind a Rawlsian “veil of ignorance” about their own personal stakes, would be able to reach a consensus on how to distribute the income of a hypothetical society. Frohlich and Oppenheimer found that the experimental groups consistently opted for striking a balance between maximizing income (providing incentives and rewards for “the fruits of one’s labors,” in the authors’ words) and ensuring that there was an economic minimum for everyone (what they called a “floor constraint”). The overall results were stunning: 77.8 percent of the groups chose to assure a minimum income for basic needs.37
The results of these important experiments, which have since been replicated many times, also lend strong support to the second of the three fairness precepts listed above concerning equity (or merit). How can we also be fair minded about rewarding our many individual differences in talents, performance, and achievements? Merit, like the term fairness itself, has an elusive quality. It does not denote some absolute standard, rather it is relational, context specific, and subject to all manner of cultural norms and practices. In general, it implies that the rewards a person receives should be proportionate to his or her effort, investment, or contribution, as Plato and Aristotle insisted.
A crucial corollary of the first two precepts, however, is that the collective survival enterprise has always been based on mutualism and reciprocity, with altruism typically being limited to special circumstances under a distinct moral claim that I refer to as “no-fault needs.” So, to balance the scale, a third precept must be added to the biosocial contract, one that puts it squarely at odds with the utopian socialists, and perhaps even with some modern social democrats as well. In any voluntary contractual arrangement, there is always reciprocity, obligations or costs as well as benefits. As I noted earlier, reciprocity is a deeply rooted part of our social psychology and an indispensable mechanism for balancing our relationships with one another.38 Without reciprocity, the first two fairness precepts might look like nothing more than a one-way scheme for redistributing wealth.
Accordingly, the three fairness precepts that I have identified (equality, equity, and reciprocity) form the goal posts for a fair society, and they are the keys to achieving the objectives of voluntary consent, social harmony, and political legitimacy.
V. HOW DO WE MEASURE UP?
Using these three fairness precepts as criteria, or measuring rods, how does our society measure up in relation to equality (providing for the basic needs of everyone), equity (rewarding merit and not subsidizing undeserved wealth), and reciprocity (a more balanced system of taxes and public service)? The answer, in a word, is relatively poorly.
A. Equality
First, let us look at equality and how well we provide for our basic needs. Once upon a time, the United States had the highest standard of living in the world, with a relatively egalitarian distribution of income and wealth, steadily declining poverty rates, and steadily improving social and health statistics. But all of this has changed radically over the past thirty years. Today, according to the Organization for Cooperation and Development (OECD), the gap between the rich and poor in the United States is the widest of any of its thirty members, except for Mexico and Turkey.39
In 2010, the top 1 percent of income earners took home 24 percent of the total national income, while the top 10 percent received almost half (49 percent).40 The distribution of wealth (including housing but excluding cars, clothes and personal furnishings) was equally skewed, with the top 1 percent owning 38 percent and the top 20 percent owning 87.2 percent.41 The remaining 12.2 percent of the wealth was shared among the other 80 percent of us.42
One indicator of this radical change over time is CEO salaries. In 1960, Fortune 500 CEOs earned forty times as much as the average worker.43 Today that figure is 320 times as much, with CEOs’ salaries (not counting other generous perks) ballooning to an average of $11.4 million, while the real wages of workers have actually declined.44 From 1980 to 2009, the median income of male high school graduates was down 25.2 percent (from $44,000 to $32,900 in 2009 dollars).45 In fact, the median income of all households is down an average of 7 percent since 2000, despite the “rising tide” at the top of the income scale.46
The result of this wide disparity in income and wealth is a nation marked by islands of ever-growing affluence surrounded by a spreading sea of deepening poverty. At the end of 2011, there were some 26 million workers who were either unemployed or underemployed, and this did not count the many millions of young people who have never been employed and cannot find jobs.47 Moreover, 47.3 percent of those who were working earned less than $25,000 per year, close to (or below) the official poverty line of $22,343 for a family of four.48 In mid-2012, some 47 million low-income Americans used food stamps, the vast majority being working poor, children, or the elderly.49 There are also currently more than 49 million Americans without health insurance.50
Judging by key health statistics, safety net programs, like unemployment insurance, food stamps, and Medicaid, only partially compensate for the destructive consequences of our extreme income and wealth inequality. In 2009, we ranked 180th among the nations of the world in infant mortality, below such countries as Cuba, Slovenia, Greece, and Portugal, and our life expectancy at birth is even worse.51 We are ranked fiftieth behind such unlikely places as San Marino, Monaco, Liechtenstein, and Cyprus, as well as every other developed nation.52 Significantly, there is also a difference of 4.5 years in average life expectancy between the bottom and top 10 percent of the population in relation to income, up from 2.8 years in 1980.53
We are also slipping badly in educating the next generation. According to the World Economic Forum, currently, less than one-third of our eighth graders are proficient in math, science and reading.54 We now rank fifty-first in the world in math education, and we are in the middle among the thirtyfour industrialized countries in science and reading test scores.55 We also rank near bottom (eighteenth out of twenty-five) in our percentage of high school graduates and fourteenth in our share of adults holding college degrees.56
Indeed, we now have a two-tiered system in which an educated, wealthy elite perpetuates itself while a vast underclass lacks the education and skills (or the money) to move up the economic escalator. This is evidenced by the fact that we have a lower level of economic mobility than most of the major industrialized countries.57 As New York Times’ columnist Nicholas Kristof puts it, today “poverty is destiny.”58 And the future looks even worse. Our states have been relentlessly slashing public school budgets, laying off teachers, and cutting school programs rather than making improvements. This is in addition to cutting unemployment benefits, tax credits for earned income, and food stamp eligibility, among other things.59
President Franklin D. Roosevelt, in his second inaugural address in 1937—in the depths of the Great Depression—declared, “I see one-third of a nation ill-housed, ill-clad, [and] ill-nourished.”60 The sad reality is that his words also ring true today, and it is time for us to face up to it. As a society, we fall far short in providing for the basic needs of our people.
B. Equity
Nor do we measure up with respect to the second fairness criterion (and the capitalist free market ideal) of equity—providing consistent economic rewards for merit. The bottom-line justification for capitalism has always been that the wealth produced has been earned by the owners and is therefore deserved by them. Moreover, it has also been justified as benefitting society, despite the wealth not being shared equally.
Often this is true, but often enough it is not true. The wealth that is generated may be unearned under any reasonable definition of the term “merit” and, in the extreme, may actually cause harm to the rest of society. It could hardly be said that “investment advisor” Bernie Madoff deserved the wealth that he skimmed from his $65 billion Ponzi scheme, or that CEO Angelo Mozilo earned the hundreds of millions of dollars that he took home from the fraudulent mortgage activities of Countrywide Financial.61 Likewise, a clear distinction must be drawn between, for example, the excessive salaries and perks of corporate CEOs, or the multi-million dollar bonuses of hedge fund managers, and any reasonable standard of economic equity (merit), especially when worker wages are being systemically reduced in many industries.
Behind the political rhetoric, and the textbook theory, our economy is also rife with what has variously been described as “crony capitalism,” “predatory capitalism,” “casino capitalism,” and market distortions like the advantages enjoyed by entrenched power and wealth and the many “barriers to entry” for entrepreneurs and the poor.62 Venture capital support for new businesses and the anti-poverty initiatives of private philanthropic foundations only partially offset these systemic biases.
C. Reciprocity
Finally, we are also deficient with respect to the reciprocity criterion. A clear implication of this fairness precept is that we are obliged to contribute a proportionate share to the collective survival enterprise in return for the benefits we receive. This applies to the rich and the poor alike—to both wealthy matrons and welfare mothers. We have a duty to reciprocate for the benefits that our society provides, otherwise we are in effect free-riding on the efforts of others; we turn them into involuntary altruists. This is one reason why, for example, the issue of “workfare”—work requirements for public welfare recipients—was an issue back in the 1990s and why the passage of welfare reform legislation that mandated a work requirement for welfare beneficiaries defused this contentious issue, although it caused some new problems, like providing adequate child care services to the poor.
A more serious violation of the principle of paying a fair share can be found in our dysfunctional tax system, which is riddled with inequities, such as oil depletion allowances, subsidies for wealthy farmers, greatly reduced “carried interest” tax rates for investment bankers, and generally regressive taxes that impose a relatively heavier burden on the middle class and the poor.
Even our federal income tax structure has become much less progressive over time. In 1951, when the American economy was booming, the top marginal tax rate was 91 percent on incomes over $1.7 million (adjusted for inflation).63 As recently as 1980, the top rate was 70 percent. In the 1990s, it was lowered to 39.6 percent.64 Then, in the 2000s, under President Bush, the rate was further reduced to 35 percent.65 Moreover, the tax rate on capital gains, which represents a significant share of the income of wealthy Americans, has recently been pegged at a flat 15 percent.66
Thus, according to the Tax Policy Center of the Brookings Institution, in 2011, the overall tax burden for the top 1 percent of taxpayers was 30 percent, while the bottom 99 percent of taxpayers had only a slightly lower rate (27.9 percent).67 In fact, about 46 percent of all “taxable units” paid no taxes at all, half of them due to various “loopholes” and “earmarks,”68 not to mention the proliferation of offshore tax havens that have sheltered many billions of dollars from income taxes altogether. In sum, we fall far short of what is required to achieve a fair society. It is time to re-write our social contract.
VI. TOWARD A NEW SOCIAL CONTRACT
What would a fair society look like? Is this an unattainable ideal? In reality, such a society would not be so different from some of the European “welfare capitalist” societies. (The current European currency/debt crisis will hopefully be fixed in due course.) Denmark, Norway, Sweden, the Netherlands, and even Germany have achieved a better balance between the three key fairness principles—to repeat: equality (providing for the basic needs of everyone), equity (rewarding merit and not subsidizing undeserved wealth), and reciprocity (a more balanced system of taxes and public service). None of these European countries is perfect, but collectively they provide a model for what is possible. Indeed, even our next-door neighbor, Canada, puts us to shame.
Steven Hill’s recent book, Europe’s Promise, goes far toward “correcting the record” about Europe for Americans.69 He calls it the “European Way.”70 Despite its current financial travails, the European Way has been very successful over the past fifty years, and it puts our own failings as a society into stark relief. It is a stinging indictment of the things we could have done much better if we had made the right choices. Here are just a few bullet points about Europe that many Americans do not know:
- The twenty-seven member European Union, with a population of 500 million (two-thirds larger than the United States), is now the world’s largest trading block, almost as large as the United States and China combined.71
- Europe’s business sector is overwhelmingly capitalist—with many more Fortune 500 companies than the United States (179 versus 140)—and includes half of the world’s sixty largest companies. Europe also accounts for more than 75 percent of all foreign investment in this country.72
- Contrary to conventional wisdom, European taxes are not a crushing burden compared to those in America. Counting Social Security and Medicare taxes, along with our state and local taxes and such hidden levies as gasoline and telephone taxes, our tax burden is very close to the rate in, say, the Netherlands, at 52 percent.73 And if you add to that our much higher out-of-pocket costs for many services that European countries subsidize, from health care to education, child care, elder care, transportation and sick leave, we actually fare much worse.74
The most distinctive feature of the European Way is its all-inclusive, cradle-to-the-grave economic security and social welfare program. Imagine a nation where there is a high level of job security, with very generous unemployment benefits, and free job retraining that is immediately available; a nation where, if you get sick, there is paid sick leave and low cost, or even free, health services; a nation where higher education is free, or very low cost; a nation where child care services are readily available at low cost, or even free, and are provided by skilled professionals; a nation where new parents are paid to stay at home and care for newborns and even receive payments to help defray the cost of diapers and extra food, among other items; and a nation where workers receive two months of vacation each year, as well as generous retirement benefits and low-cost elder and nursing care. As Steven Hill says in his book, “To most Americans, such a place sounds like Never, Never Land. But to most Europeans, . . . America is the outlier.”75
What can be done to reform our own dysfunctional society? First, we as a nation need to undertake a national full employment program that is committed to providing productive jobs for everyone who is able to work, and with a “living wage,” not our delusional minimum wage. (This would further all three fairness precepts at once.) It would, of course, require a sustained, multi-faceted effort, including a public-private partnership. There are a many areas where adding more jobs would be socially productive, from re-hiring laid off teachers, firefighters, and health care workers to creating jobs for construction workers—in order to make badly needed infrastructure improvements (decrepit roads, bridges, dams, sewers, etc.)— and the technicians needed to help develop leading-edge technologies.
Beyond this, we must progressively increase our minimum wage to a more realistic level (Washington State currently leads the way with a state minimum wage of just over $9 per hour).76 Some theorists believe a gradual minimum wage increase to $15 per hour, with some targeted exceptions, would be justified. This would go far toward ensuring that everyone’s basic needs are provided for without handouts. Moreover, the benefits would be earned and therefore consistent with the equity (merit) precept.
Equally important, we must greatly strengthen the “safety net” for the many people in our society who cannot work, including the extremely old, the very young, and those with various “no-fault” needs, like those who are severely disabled and sick. Improvements to public services like transportation, and especially education, are also imperative, along with repairs to our deteriorating infrastructure. A commitment to providing for the basic needs of all our citizens is affordable, even as we are paying down our national debt. All that is needed is the political will provide for citizens’ needs by selectively increasing taxes and eliminating tax loopholes.77 There is much more on this in my book.78
Our capitalist system must also be reformed in order to align it more closely with merit (equity). The model going forward should be “stakeholder capitalism.”79 As the term implies, this is a kind of capitalism in which all of the stakeholders are empowered and can influence the way a business operates—the workers, the customers, the community, the suppliers, and even the government (mostly through regulations and incentives)—not just the owners and shareholders who predominate in our form of capitalism. This would change the balance of power and, as a result, the operative values of capitalist enterprises. Examples of companies that practice stakeholder capitalism can be found even now in our society. I describe one, the farmer-owned Organic Valley food company, in the book, and there are many more examples both here and in other countries.
To balance the benefits with a comparable obligation for reciprocity, there needs to be a top-to-bottom reform of our corrupt tax system. Yes, the rich will end up paying more (their fair share), and there will also be an end to the cornucopia of tax breaks, subsidies, loopholes, and dubious incentives. And yes, we also have to “fix” Social Security, Medicare and Medicaid, but not with “reforms” that are in fact a hidden agenda for privatizing and destroying these programs. Beyond this, the long-simmering idea of a broad, national public service program that asks everyone to give back to our society with their time and talents could have a transformative cultural influence.
Finally, to achieve all this, we need major structural reforms in our broken political system—elimination of the filibuster rule in the Senate; reductions in the power of money in our politics; reforms to our election campaign financing system; non-partisan redistricting to eliminate gerrymandering; restrictions on the “revolving door” between government and the private sector; and more.
A. The Ball Is in Our Court
All of this is, of course, only a sketch. There are many more ideas (perhaps even better ideas) out there for what could be done to affect a major course change in our society, but none of this can be accomplished without visionary and inspiring leadership and a powerful wave of public support. What is needed going forward is an “Occupy Washington” movement armed with the demand for a “Fair Society”—a sweeping reform platform that could win a clear electoral mandate for the necessary changes. Such reforms have happened before in our history, with antitrust legislation, the minimum wage, collective bargaining rights for workers, Social Security and Medicare, civil rights, women’s rights, accommodations for Americans with disabilities, and more.
In short, there are numerous precedents for positive changes, and there is every reason to believe that it can happen again. As political scientists Jacob Hacker and Paul Pierson point out in their 2010 book, Winner-Take-All Politics, it was politics that got us into this mess, and politics can get us out of it.80 But we are the only ones who can make it happen. As the television host and commentator Bill Moyers put it, “The only answer to organized money is organized people.”81 The ball is in our court.
FOOTNOTES
-
Director of the Institute for the Study of Complex Systems. Also a one-time science writer for Newsweek, a professor in Human Biology at Stanford University, and the author of several previous books. See, e.g., PETER CORNING, THE SYNERGISM HYPOTHESIS: A THEORY OF PROGRESSIVE EVOLUTION (1983); PETER CORNING, NATURE’S MAGIC: SYNERGY IN EVOLUTION AND THE FATE OF HUMANKIND (2003); PETER CORNING, HOLISTIC DARWINISM: SYNERGY, CYBERNETICS AND THE BIOECONOMICS OF EVOLUTION (2005). This article is drawn from the author’s most recent book, PETER CORNING, THE FAIR SOCIETY: THE SCIENCE OF HUMAN NATURE AND THE FATE OF HUMANKIND (2011).
-
Ben White, What Red Ink? Wall Street Paid Hefty, N.Y. TIMES, Jan. 28, 2009, www.nytimes.com/2009/01/29/business/29bonus.html.
-
Chris Isidore, Americans Lost Trillions, CNN MONEY, June 9, 2011, http://money.cnn.com/2011/06/09/news/economy/household_wealth/index.htm; Mortimer B. Zuckerman, The Great Jobs Recession Goes On, U.S. NEWS, Feb. 11, 2011, http://www.usnews.com/opinion/mzuckerman/articles/2011/02/11/the-great-jobsrecession-goes-on; Emergency Economic Stabilization Act of 2008, WIKIPEDIA, http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Emergency_Economic_Stabilization_Act_of_2008 (last modified May 23, 2012).
-
Full Text of President Obama’s Economic Speech in Osawatomie, Kans., WASH. POST, Dec. 6, 2011, http://www.washingtonpost.com/politics/president-obamaseconomic-speech-in-osawatomie-kans/2011/12/06/gIQAVhe6ZO_story.html.
-
Jason DeParle et al., Older, Suburban and Struggling, ‘Near Poor’ Startle the Census, N.Y. TIMES, Nov. 18, 2011, http://www.nytimes.com/2011/11/19/us/census-measuresthose-not-quite-in-poverty-but-struggling.html?pagewanted=all; see also Sabrina Tavernise, Soaring Poverty Casts Spotlight on ‘Lost Decade,’ N.Y. TIMES, Sept. 13, 2011, http://www.nytimes.com/2011/09/14/us/14census.html?pagewanted=all.
-
See CORNING, THE FAIR SOCIETY, supra note 1.
-
Golden Rule, WIKIPEDIA, http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/The_Golden_Rule_(ethics) (last modified May 21, 2012).
-
Brain Imaging Study Sheds Light on Moral Decision-Making, SCI. DAILY (Sept. 14, 2001), http://www.sciencedaily.com/releases/2001/09/010914074303.htm.
-
Alan G. Sanfey, Social Decision-Making: Insights from Game Theory and Neuroscience, 318 SCI. 598 (2007), available at http://www.sciencemag.org/content/ 318/5850/598.full.
-
Paul Zak, Guest Post, Economist as Therapist, FREAKONOMICS (May 3, 2010), http://www.freakonomics.com/2010/05/03/is-there-a-moral-molecule-a-guest-post-fromneuroeconomist-paul-zak/.
-
Id.
-
DONALD E. BROWN, HUMAN UNIVERSALS 130–141 (1991).
-
CORNING, THE FAIR SOCIETY, supra note 1.
-
See generally HERBERT GINTIS ET AL., MORAL SENTIMENTS AND MATERIAL INTERESTS: THE FOUNDATIONS OF COOPERATION IN ECONOMIC LIFE (2005); Herbert Gintis & Ernst Fehr, Human Motivation and Social Cooperation: Experimental and Analytical Foundations, 33 ANN. REV. SOC. 43 (2007); Herbert Gintis, Punishment and Cooperation, 319 SCI. 1345, 1345–46 (2008).
-
FRANS DE WAAL, THE AGE OF EMPATHY: NATURE’S LESSONS FOR A KINDER SOCIETY 5–7 (2009).
-
Jessica C. Flack & Frans de Waal, ‘Any Animal Whatever’ Darwinian Building Blocks of Morality in Monkeys and Apes, 7 J. CONSCIOUSNESS STUD. 1 (2005), available at http://www.emory.edu/LIVING_LINKS/pdf_attachments/Flack_deWaal_moral.pdf.
-
Samuel Bowles & Herbert Gintis, Is Equality Passé?: Homo Reciprocans and the Future of Egalitarian Politics, BOSTON REV., Dec. 1998–Jan. 1999, available at http://bostonreview.net/BR23.6/bowles.html. This is also a consistent finding in the research on strong reciprocity theory. CORNING, THE FAIR SOCIETY, supra note 1, at 6.
-
See PLATO, THE REPUBLIC (World Publ’g Co. 1946).
-
ARISTOTLE, NICHOMACHEAN ETHICS 75 (Hackett 1985).
-
See THOMAS HOBBES, LEVIATHAN: ON THE MATTER FORM AND POWER OF A COMMONWEALTH ECCLESIASTICAL AND CIVIL (Collier Books 1962).
-
See JOHN L. LOCKE, TWO TREATISES OF GOVERNMENT (Harvard Univ. Press 1970).
-
DAVID HUME, A TREATISE OF HUMAN NATURE 529 (Clarendon Press 1987).
-
See JOHN RAWLS, A THEORY OF JUSTICE (Belknap Press 1971)
-
KEN BINMORE, NATURAL JUSTICE 157–58 (2005).
-
CORNING, THE FAIR SOCIETY, supra note 1, at 80.
-
Id. at 171.
-
Id. at 87–112
-
Id.
-
Id. at 27 (providing examples)
-
3 See, e.g., CECILE FABRE, SOCIAL RIGHTS UNDER THE CONSTITUTION: GOVERNMENT AND THE DECENT LIFE (2000). The desirability, or lack thereof, of bills of rights has been the focus of some of the most enduring political debates over the last two centuries. Unlike civil and political rights, social rights to the meeting of needs, standard rights to adequate minimum income, education, housing, and health care are usually not given constitutional protection. The book argues that individuals have social rights to adequate minimum income, housing, health care, and education, and that those rights must be entrenched in the constitution of a democratic state. That is, the democratic majority should not be able to repeal them, and certain institutions (for instance, the judiciary) should be given the power to strike down laws passed by the legislature that are in breach of those rights. Thus, the book is located at the crossroads of two major issues of contemporary political philosophy, to wit, the issue of democracy and the issue of distributive justice. Id.
-
The Universal Declaration included social (or “welfare”) rights that address matters such as education, food, and employment, though their inclusion has been the source of much controversy. See, e.g., David Beetham, What Future for Economic and Social Rights?, POL. STUD. 41 (1995), available at http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/ j.1467-9248.1995.tb01735.x/pdf.
-
The European Social Charter treaty, enacted by the Council of Europe in 1961, guaranteed economic and social rights. European Social Charter, COUNCIL OF EUR., http://www.coe.int/T/DGHL/Monitoring/SocialCharter/ (last visited May 27, 2012).
-
Article 1 of the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights, adopted by the General Assembly in 1966 and entered into force ten years later, declared in part as follows: “In no case may a people be deprived of its own means of subsistence.” International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights, adopted Dec. 16, 1966, 993 U.N.T.S. 3 (entered into force Jan. 3, 1976), available at http://www2.ohchr.org/english/law/cescr.htm (last visited May 25, 2012). This covenant also enumerates a list of specific rights, including nondiscrimination and equality for women in the economic and social arena (Articles 2 and 3), freedom to work and opportunities to work (Article 4), fair pay and decent conditions of work (Article 7), theright to form trade unions and to strike (Article 8), social security (Article 9), special protections for mothers and children (Article 10), the right to adequate food, clothing, and housing (Article 11), the right to basic health services (Article 12), the right to education (Article 13), and the right to participate in cultural life and scientific progress (Article 15). Id.
-
For a more detailed discussion of social rights, see James Nickel, Human Rights, STAN. ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHIL. (Fall 2010), available at http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/rightshuman/#EcoSocRig.
-
CORNING, THE FAIR SOCIETY, supra note 1, at 155–56.
-
See NORMAN FROHLICH & JOE A. OPPENHEIMER, CHOOSING JUSTICE: AN EXPERIMENTAL APPROACH TO ETHICAL THEORY (1992).
-
CORNING, THE FAIR SOCIETY, supra note 1, at 156.
-
Id. at 87–112.
-
Society: Governments Must Tackle Record Gap Between Rich and Poor, Says OECD, ORG. FOR ECON. CO-OPERATION & DEV. (May 12, 2011), htttp://www.oecd.org/document/40/0,3746,en_21571361_44315115_49166760_1_1_1_1,00.html.
-
See Sylvia A. Allegretto, The State of Working America’s Wealth, 2011: Through Volatility and Turmoil, the Gap Widens, State of Working America, ECON. POL’Y INST. (Mar. 23, 2011), http://www.irle.berkeley.edu/cwed/wp/wealth_in_the_us.pdf; Income Inequality in the United States, WIKIPEDIA, http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/ Income_inequality_in_the_United_States (last modified May 25, 2012).
-
Id.
-
Id.
-
History of Corporate Executive Wages, EBSCOHOST.COM, http://connection.ebscohost.com/ (last visited Sept. 23, 2012)
-
CEO Pay and the 99%, AM. FED’N LAB. & CONGRESS INDUS. ORGS., http://www.aflcio.org/Corporate-Watch/CEO-Pay-and-the-99 (last visited May 23, 2012).
-
See Allegretto, supra note 40; Income Inequality in the United States, supra note 40.
-
Dennis Cauchon & Barbara Hansen, Typical U.S. Family Got Poorer During the Past 10 Years, USA TODAY, Sept. 14, 2011, http://www.usatoday.com/news/nation/story/ 2011-09-13/census-household-income/50383882/1; Fast Facts: Income of Young Adults, NAT’L CTR. FOR EDUC. STAT., http://nces.ed.gov/fastfacts/display.asp?id=77 (last visited May 27, 2012).Ben Baden, The Ranks of the Underemployed Continue to Grow, U.S. NEWS & WORLD REPORT (Oct. 19, 2011), http://money.usnews.com/money/careers/articles/ 2011/10/19/the-ranks-of-the-underemployed-continue-to-grow.
-
Peter Corning, “How to Lie with Statistics,” FAIR SOCIETY (Nov. 28, 2011), http://www.thefairsociety.net/2011_11_01_archive.html.
-
Jeff Cox, Report: 15% of Americans on Foodstamps, NBCNEWS.COM (Sept. 5, 2012), http://bottomline.nbcnews.com/_news/2012/09/05/13682742-report-15-of-americans-onfood-stamps?lite.
-
CORNING, THE FAIR SOCIETY, supra note 1, at 115–17.
-
CIA–The World Fact Book—Rank Order–Infant Mortality Rate, NUMBRARY, http://numbrary.com/sources/2c473cae74-cia-the-world-factbook (last visited June 3, 2012).
-
Country Comparison: Life Expectancy at Birth, CIA WORLD FACTBOOK, https://www.cia.gov/library/publications/the-world-factbook/rankorder/2102rank.html (last visited June 1, 2012).
-
53 Elise Gould, Growing Disparities in Life Expectancy, ECON. POL’Y INST. (July 16, 2008), http://www.epi.org/publication/webfeatures_snapshots_20080716/.
-
54 The Global Competitiveness Forum 2011–2012, WORLD ECON. FORUM (Klaus Schwab ed., 2011), available at http://www3.weforum.org/docs/ WEF_GCR_Report_2011-12.pdf.
-
Id.
-
Louis Jacobson, Laura Tyson Correct that U.S. Lags in College Graduation Rates But Overstates Severity of High School Dropout Rates, POLITIFACT (Aug. 17, 2010), http://www.politifact.com/truth-o-meter/statements/2010/aug/17/laura-tyson/laura-tysoncorrect-us-lag-college-grads-overstate/.
-
Dan Froomkin, Social Immobility: Climbing The Economic Ladder Is Harder In The U.S. Than In Most European Countries, HUFFINGTON POST (Sept. 21, 2010), http://www.huffingtonpost.com/2010/03/17/social-immobility-climbin_n_501788.html.
-
Peter Corning, The American Dream: Time to Wakeup, FAIR SOCIETY (Jan. 19, 2012), http://www.thefairsociety.net/2012_01_01_archive.html.
-
Nicholas Johnson et al., An Update on State Budget Cuts: At Least 46 States Have Imposed Cuts That Hurt Vulnerable Residents and the Economy, CTR. ON BUDGET & POL’Y PRIORITIES (Feb. 9, 2011), http://www.cbpp.org/cms/ index.cfm?fa=view&id=1214.
-
President Franklin D. Roosevelt, Second Inaugural Address (Jan. 20, 1937), available at http://avalon.law.yale.edu/20th_century/froos2.asp.
-
Bernard Madoff, WIKIPEDIA, en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Bernard_Madoff (last modified Oct. 9, 2012); Angela Mozilo, WIKIPEDIA, http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Angelo_Mozilo (last modified Oct. 10, 2012).
-
See CORNING, THE FAIR SOCIETY, supra note 1; JAMES K. GALBRAITH, THE PREDATOR STATE: HOW CONSERVATIVES ABANDONED THE FREE MARKET AND WHY LIBERALS SHOULD TOO (2008); JOSEPH E. STIGLITZ, FREEFALL: AMERICA, MARKETS, AND THE SINKING OF THE WORLD ECONOMY (2010).
-
U.S. Federal Individual Income Tax Rates History, 1913–2011, TAX FOUND., http://taxfoundation.org/article/us-federal-individual-income-tax-rates-history-1913- 2011-nominal-and-inflation-adjusted-brackets (last visited Sept. 23, 2012).
-
Id.
-
Id.
-
Capital Gains Tax in the United States, WIKIPEDIA, http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Capital_gains_tax_in_the_United_States (last updated June 3, 2012).
-
Rachel M. Johnson et al., Why Some Tax Units Pay No Taxes, TAX POL’Y CTR. (July 2011), http://www.urban.org/publications/1001547.html.
-
Id.
-
STEVEN HILL, EUROPE’S PROMISE: WHY THE EUROPEAN WAY IS THE BEST HOPE IN AN INSECURE AGE (2010).
-
Id.
-
Id. at 35, 95, 206.
-
Id.
-
Id.
-
Id.
-
Steven Hill, The Missing Element of Obama’s Economic Plan, OPENDEMOCRACY, http://www.opendemocracy.net/authors/steven-hill (last visited Oct. 12, 2012).
-
Announcement, Washington State Department of Labor & Industries, 2012 Minimum Wage Announcement (Dec. 8, 2011), available at www.lni.wa.gov/workplacerights/ files/2012MinimumWageAnnouncement.pdf.
-
CORNING, THE FAIR SOCIETY, supra note 1, at 169–94.
-
Id.
-
See STAKEHOLDER CAPITALISM 185–201 (Gavin Kelly et al. eds., 1997).
-
See generally JACOB S. HACKER & PAUL PIERSON, WINNER-TAKE-ALL POLITICS: HOW WASHINGTON MADE THE RICH RICHER—AND TURNED ITS BACK ON THE MIDDLE CLASS (2010).
-
Bill Moyers, The Journal: Reform vs. Reformation (PBS television broadcast Mar. 26, 2010), available at http://www.pbs.org/moyers/journal/03262010/watch3.html.